In
‘Postscript on Societies of Control’, Deleuze marks the passing of the
“Disciplinary Society”. These societies operated on localisable, hierarchical
topologies idealised in the model of the factory: ‘bringing everything
together, giving each thing its place, organizing time, setting up in this
space-time a force of production greater than the sum of component forces’
(Deleuze, 1995: 177). Their passing signifies not just the “breaking down”
(Deleuze, 1995: 182) of old institutions, but the introduction of the “Control
Society”, characterised by ‘ultrarapid forms of apparently free-floating
control that are taking over from the old disciplines at work within the time
scales of closed systems’ (Deleuze, 1995: 178). The topology of these new mechanisms of power, unlike the
centralized uniformity of the factory, are diffuse, molecular, and networked.
Galloway and Thacker identify one of the characteristics of this society as
the, ‘increasing everydayness of surveillance’ (Galloway and Thacker, 2007: 15)
through the likes of webcams, CCTV, spyware, UAVs, and, perhaps most pertinent
today, the mechanisms of surveillance on social media such as data collection.
This indicates a shift away from the localisation and fixity of power
relations, towards a nomadic and networked practices.
As such,
the idea of “place” seems antiquated in modern discourse, almost luddite in its
insistence on a conceivable, bounded spatial configuration, which can be
individuated from a network. With the innumerable cross-currents and flows that
permeate borderlands, the continual flux of actants which, voluntarily and
involuntarily, are moved through places, and the omnipresence of control
mechanisms, “place” appears as a non-concept to Control Societies. The
redundancy of place is analogous to the process of globalization, mirrored in
Marc Augé’s anthropology of supermodernity and the production of non-places,
‘spaces which are not themselves anthropological places and which […] do not
integrate the earlier places’ (Augé, 1995: 78). These range from the likes of
supermarkets, to airports, motorways, and as such are characterised by transit
and an erasure of identity, they are spaces of absolute control. Their
proliferation is a signpost of the status of “place” in contemporary life.
However, a
regression towards earlier models of place-centred thought could pose huge
risks for the progression of “supermodernity” and especially the struggle
against its dominant rationality; Neoliberalism. The anti-globalist argument against supermodernity, seen in
the likes of anti-capitalist activism, focuses on specific places as sites of
enchantment, possessing some sort of stable identity and functioning as sites of
memory. It is also, however, often utilised by regressive, right-wing and
nativist actants. The link between identity and place is one that bears too
many scars from the totalitarian regimes of the twentieth century, as well as
their resurgent reactionary forms. Arguing for “place” against “non-place” can
seem, in the face of an already globalised, “disenchanted” world, futile at
best and dangerous at worst. The argument is also ignorant of the current
political topology of symmetry which Galloway and Thacker identify, of
“networks fighting networks” (Galloway and Thacker, 2007: 15), the political
priority of the network undermines the significance of any one place.
Rather, the emphasis today is on spatial practice and invisibility, like Hakim
Bey’s Temporary Autonomous Zone, ‘[a]s soon as the TAZ is named
(represented, mediated), it must vanish, it will vanish, leaving behind
it an empty husk, only to spring up again somewhere else, once again invisible
because undefinable in terms of the Spectacle’ (Bey, 2017).
This essay
will argue that, in fact, place is not a regressive concept, but one that is
entirely relevant to not just political activism, but the continuing practice
of everyday life. To justify this claim, this essay will examine the role that
place plays in several influential philosophical texts, including Michel de
Certeau’s The Practice of Everyday Life, Martin Heidegger’s ‘Building Dwelling Thinking’, and the disparate,
but sustained engagement with space in the work of Michel Foucault. At
first, the subject-centred method of someone like Heidegger seems incompatible
with the anti-phenomenology of modern materialist thought. However, I wish to
show that an experiential mode of place, rather than contradicting the
de-localising tendencies of modern theory, can work with it. In other words;
place can be utilised as a vital
concept in strategies against control societies. Part of my aim is to expand
this reconceptualization to encompass not just short-term activist practices
but place on a much broader, everyday scale.
Whilst
this subject may at first seem too broad in its horizons, attempting to
reconfigure an already much written about topic to assimilate a variety of
modern theory, this essay will seek to make place a focused and practical
concept. Its primary objective is to identify the role that place can play in
the shifting topologies of a society in which power operates on a covert,
diffuse level. “Space” is a concept with a much wider usage in contemporary
critical theory and thought. Not only does this word appeal to the
“topological” and “diagrammatic” thinking of Deleuze and materialist thought,
but also to ideas of “social space” and spatial production as expounded by the
likes of Marxist-Urban theorists like Lefebvre and de Certeau.
Place, in
comparison, is an uneasy concept in its conservationist fixity. Yet Edward
Casey argues for its ontological priority, ‘place serves as the condition of
all existing things. This means that, far from being merely locatory or
situational, place belongs to the very concept of existence. To be is to be
bounded by place, limited by it’ (Casey, 1993: 15). As such, place is an
inescapable category of critical enquiry. However, the boundaries that Casey
distinguishes are not negative limitations, but positive presences, ‘intrinsic
to [something’s] being, a condition for its very existing’ (Casey, 1993: 15).
The emphasis on this positivity provides glimpses threads towards a more
vitalist approach that resonates with modern theory.
The
relationship of space to place is not oppositional, as de Certeau demonstrates
in The Practice of Everyday Life; Whilst place ‘is the order in accord
with which elements are distributed in relationships of coexistence’ and thus
‘an instantaneous configuration of positions [which] implies an indication of
stability’, space, on the other hand, ‘is composed of intersections of mobile
elements. It is in a sense actuated by the ensemble of movements deployed
within it’, consequently; ‘space is a practiced place’. He gives an
example of this differentiation: ‘the street geometrically defined by urban
planning is transformed into a space by walkers’ (de Certeau, 1988: 117).
Compared to the “positive presence” that place elicits in Casey’s formulation,
for de Certeau it appears almost as a negative influence; a stable order
imposed from above, liberated only by the practice of spatial production. The
power relations implicit in this conceptualisation problematises an immediate
reconfiguration of place, undermining its potential as a liberational mode of
political engagement.
The
“stability” of place, as posited by de Certeau, indicates not just a
reproduction of social relations, but also the legitimation of surveillance in
accordance with control societies. If a place is imposed from above, then the
fixity of that place will be reliant on its mechanisms of power. An interesting
case study which might help to illustrate this is the modern music festival.
Whilst originally conceived as spaces of liminality and absolute ‘freedom from
work and social norms’ (Friedler, 2018), the modern music festival has
undergone a series of inconspicuous transformations which correspond with this
authorial fixity. From the implementation of trackable wristbands, perimeter
fences patrolled by guards, “SkyCop towers” and surveillance drones with facial
recognition technology, these localised mechanisms mark this transition
These measures keep us trapped in the
fest, a concentrated zone of consumption. You have no choice but to buy from
the vendors, to watch artists perform beneath logos. As temperatures soar over
100 degrees, sponsored activities are tied to survival: Cool off in the
Heineken igloo! Skip the water lines by liking H&M on Facebook!
(Friedler, 2018)
These “security” tactics are
justified by a manufactured public anxiety over terrorist attacks, which arise
from the technology of connectivity, as Galloway and Thacker show, ‘Bomb
threats and terror alerts inject intangible anxiety into the population just as
a real bomb might do. […] Without connectivity, terrorism would not exist in
its current form’ (Galloway and Thacker, 2007: 16). As such, the move from
Disciplinary to Control society results not in a redundancy of place, but a
re-signification of it. The modern music festival is conceived with these
mechanisms of control inscribed into its architecture; the stability of the
towers, the control of the drone, the traceability of the wristbands, the
display of logos, they all relationally coexist as a distributed series of
elements (to refigure de Certeau’s definition of place) which exists separately
from the spatial practices of festival-goers. But, this also prompts the
question of whether they exist independently of spatial practices.
This
relationship between place and spatial practice, architecture and the
experience of architecture, is touched upon in an interview with Foucault,
‘Space, Knowledge, and Power’. When asked whether he sees any possibility of an
architecture of liberation or resistance, he responds
I do not think that it is possible to
say that one thing is of the order of “liberation” and another is of the order
of “oppression.” There are a certain number of things that one can say with
some certainty about a concentration camp, to the effect that it is not an instrument
of liberation, but one should still take into account - and this is not
generally acknowledged - that, aside from torture and execution which preclude
any resistance, no matter how terrifying a given system may be, there always
remain the possibilities of resistance, disobedience, and oppositional
groupings.
(Foucault, 2002: 354)
Again, this differentiates
place from spatial practice, here identified as “resistance, disobedience, and
oppositional groupings”. He later elaborates, ‘[...] I do not think that there
is anything that is functionally - by its very nature - absolutely liberating.
Liberty is a practice’ (Foucault, 2002: 354). It is also significant
that Foucault finds an architecture of absolute “oppression” impossible. Whilst
this on the one hand allows for the activity of resistance and disobedience, it
also establishes for architecture the capacity for indeterminacy, and therefore
for place to be indeterminate.
This
slippage between “stability” and indeterminacy also complicates the relationship
between place and spatial practice. In the article about Coachella, for
instance, Frieder identifies the spatial practice as an “ironic embrace” of
Capitalism, ‘[w]e tag sponsored content and tweet back at brands’ (Frieder,
2018). Yet, one must question if these spatial practices are assimilated back
into the genius loci of a place. One must also question the role of
place-making in the festival prior to corporate sponsorship and the invasion of
control mechanisms; the original utopian vision of the music festival.
Whilst unable to permanently fix liberation into its architecture, its creation
coincided and facilitated the spatial practices of liberation. The practices of
place-making and spatial practice are interwoven, as Foucault goes on to say
I think it is somewhat arbitrary to try
to dissociate the effective practice of freedom by people, the practice of
social relations, and the spatial distributions in which they find themselves.
If they are separated, they become impossible to understand. Each can only be
understood through the other.
(Foucault, 2002: 356)
This is true not only in the
duality of control mechanisms and spatial practice, but in the oneness of
place-making and spatial practice. Whilst control mechanisms can be inscribed
into the architecture, they cannot wholly define that place. Indeed, place
retains a hesitant indeterminacy which accords with the contingency that
Foucault describes. Analogous to de Certeau’s formulation, place and space are
not opposites, but connected by processes of time and agency. The
“instantaneous” presence of place facilitates the contingency of spatial
practice.
However,
the “instantaneous” presence of place also ignores its pre-history and making.
Whilst de Certeau is concerned with proving the non-passivity of citizens, he does not go far enough in
uniting spatial practice with place-making, which is important for the
conceptual reconfiguration that this essay proposes. This concept of
place-making needs to be further differentiated to distinguish the subjectivity
of various actants and their efficacy. Whilst thus far in this essay it has
been solely the activity of those with power and authority; architects and
planners, in ‘Building Dwelling Thinking’, Heidegger discusses the qualities of
place-making intrinsic to being, which greatly widens its conceptual scope.
For
Heidegger, rather than “building” being a means towards “dwelling”, the two
terms are innate to one another, ‘[w]e do not dwell because we have built, but
we build and have built because we dwell, that is, because we are dwellers’.
As such, dwelling is, ‘the manner in which mortals are on the earth’
(Heidegger, 2013: 146). Through an act of linguistic archaeology, Heidegger
identifies the Old English and High German word for building, “buan”, which
also means to dwell. Through the inescapable act of dwelling, we are also
builders. However, building in this sense does not entail manual labour as
such, but rather a bringing of the “fourfold”[1] into a location
Dwelling preserves the fourfold by
bringing the presencing of the fourfold into things. But things themselves
secure the fourfold only when they themselves as things are let
be in their presencing. How is this done? In this way, that mortals nurse and
nurture the things that grow, and specially construct things that do not grow.
Cultivating and construction are building in the narrower sense. Dwelling,
insofar as it keeps or secures the fourfold in things, is, as this keeping, a
building.
(Heidegger, 2013: 149)
Whilst the mystical
implications of the fourfold, alongside the decidedly provincial nature of
Heidegger’s writing, seems inconsequential to the more urban slant of de
Certeau’s ideas, considering “building” not in terms of physical construction,
but as the positive presence of dwelling, has radical implications for spatial
practice. Like de Certeau, Heidegger sees spaces as deriving from place,
‘[s]pace is in essence that for which room has been made, that which is let
into its bounds. That for which room is made is always granted and hence is
joined, that is, gathered, by virtue of a location’ (Heidegger, 2013: 152).
Yet, rather than existing apart from places, we contribute to the ongoing
creation of those places through time. Heidegger also posits, like Casey, the
ontological priority of situatedness, ‘we always go through spaces in such a
way that we already experience them by staying constantly with near and
remote locations and things [emphasis added]’ (Heidegger, 2013: 155). This is
not to contradict de Certeau’s “instantaneous coexistence” of place, as
Heidegger still regards our movements relative to places as a form of spatial
practice. But, in emphasising the constancy of our “staying with things” and
the productive nature of dwelling, one cannot help but re-read “place” from the
bottom up. Instead of places being imposed from above, their creation is
intrinsic to our being.
An example
of this form of place-making can be found in William Wordsworth’s ‘Poems of the
Naming of Places’; for instance, in ‘To Joanna’, the narrator is inspired to
carve the name of his muse into a rock where they had once travelled through,
‘And I, and all who dwell by my fireside, / Have called the lovely rock,
Joanna’s Rock’ (Wordsworth, 2006:
172). Like many of Wordsworth’s other poems, the place on which he reflects is
discovered through travel, ‘One summer morning we had walked abroad / At break
of day, Joanna and myself’ (Wordsworth, 2006: 171). After coming to a place
called “Rotha’s banks”, the narrator stops to contemplate the scene, ‘Joanna,
looking in my eyes, beheld / That ravishment of mine, and laughed aloud. / The
Rock, like something starting from a sleep, / Took up the Lady’s voice, and
laughed again…’ Then
...long afterwards, when eighteen moons
Were wasted, as I chanced to walk alone
Beneath this rock, at sunrise, on a
calm
And silent morning, I sat down, and
there
In memory of affections old and true,
I chiselled out in those rude
characters
Joanna’s name deep in the living stone…
(Wordsworth, 2006: 171-172)
The narrator’s act of graffiti,
rather than existing as a spatial practice within the confines of a location,
is, in fact, productive of a new location. One could imagine this narrative
transposed onto an urban setting with still the same effect. Whilst he is
already at a place called “Rotha’s banks”, he creates another place which sits
within it. Like the fourfold intrinsic to Heidegger’s dwelling, the narrator’s
building stems from “memory of affections old and true”, a response to the being-there
described in the poem. This act of memory and affection establishes a
phenomenological basis for a place to be made, but also draws attention to the
temporal grounding of places indicated in the “mortality” of the fourfold,
‘[m]ortals dwell in that they initiate their own nature - their being capable
of death as death’ (Heidegger, 2013: 148). The fixity of place is profound due
to the absolute un-fixity of human life.
Yet this
fixity, as Heidegger shows, requires a consistent act of dwelling, a “staying
with things”, which reflects the conservationist concerns of Wordsworth. In a
note at the end of the poem, Wordsworth notes that real inscriptions on the
rock have faded ‘from the wasting of time’ (Wordsworth, 2006: 172). The
combination of the graffiti and the poem, which captures the phenomenological
act of dwelling intrinsic to the place, convey an underlying anxiety about this
“wasting of time” and the contingency inherent to location. Casey expands on
the necessity of time to place, ‘There is no (grasping of) time without
place; and this is so precisely by virtue of place’s actively delimiting
and creatively conditioning capacities. Place situates time by giving it a
local habitation’ (Casey, 1993: 21). By creating a place Wordsworth realises
his own mortality, but in the supposedly mimetic act of poetry, he attempts to
stave off its contingency by creating another place in words. Yet, as Heidegger
writes
Even when we relate ourselves to those
things that are not in our immediate reach, we are staying with the things
themselves. We do not represent distant things merely in our mind - as the
textbooks have it - so that only mental representations of distant things run
through our minds and heads as substitutes for things. If all of us now think,
from where we are right here, of the old bridge in Heidelberg, this thinking
toward that location is not a mere experience inside the persons present here;
rather, it belongs to the nature of our thinking of that bridge that in
itself thinking gets through, persists through, the distance to that
location.
(Heidegger, 2013: 154)
Thinking of a place is
analogous to dwelling, but this raises a vital point as to the existential
qualities of place. The act of thinking about place isn’t representational, as
Heidegger shows, meaning that Wordsworth’s poem isn’t exactly mimetic in the
sense that it mirrors place. Rather, the spatial practice of mimesis at work in
the poem aids the production of “Joanna’s Rock” and situates it amongst
locations which already exist (i.e. Rotha’s bank); in accordance with the idea
that place is exclusively the product of dwelling. In short to name and/or
think of a place is to construct that place.
Hence,
there is an indeterminate obscurity in the combined act of naming places and
recognising the Ozymandian contingency of those places. The conservationist
tendencies implicit in both Heidegger’s thought and Wordsworth’s poetry almost
seems to work against (or, because of) this contingency by asserting the
sovereignty of the individual to fix places in time. The mystical aspects of
Heidegger’s fourfold, whilst bringing a sense of Romanticism to place, fails to
justify its value to modern theory and the need for an exploit to Control
Societies. Whilst in de Certeau, there is, rather, a playfulness to this
fixity. For him, place names, ‘create a nowhere in places; they change them
into passages’ (de Certeau, 1988: 104). This adheres to a spatial practice, but
de Certeau goes further
...these names make themselves
available to the diverse meanings given them by passers-by; they detach
themselves from the places they were supposed to define and serve as imaginary
meeting-points on itineraries which, as metaphors, they determine for reasons
that are foreign to their original value but may be recognized or not by
passers-by. A strange toponymy that is detached from actual places and flies
high over the city like a foggy geography of “meanings” held in suspension,
directing the physical deambulations below…
(de Certeau, 1988: 104)
There is a recognisable overlap
between the function of names to “make themselves available to diverse
meanings” and the Romantic unity of naming and building. Indeed, de Certeau
states that these proper names of places possess “magic power”, and thus are
left open to the indeterminacy of a multiplicity of subjective experiences. The
“constellations” of names behaves in much a similar way as the networked,
nomadic subjectivity of Deleuze, but de Certeau charges the individual,
localisable nodes with anarchic power:
Linking acts and footsteps, opening
meanings and directions, these words operate in the name of an emptying-out and
wearing-away of their primary role. They become liberated spaces that can be
occupied. A rich indetermination gives them, by means of a semantic
rarefaction, the function of articulating a second, poetic geography on top of
the geography of the literal, forbidden or permitted meaning.
(de Certeau, 1988: 105)
This “second” geography is also
hinted at in the “territorial gangsterism” of Bey, ‘[n]ot one square inch of
Earth goes unpoliced or untaxed… in theory’ (Bey, 2017). The attempts to capture place, be it
in the country or the city, cannot ever be finalised as, “[o]nly psychotopography can
draw 1:1 maps of reality because only the human mind provides sufficient
complexity to model the real’ (Bey, 2017). Here, Bey perhaps has too much faith
in the “human mind”, the experience and naming of places is also itself a form
of map-making.
Although,
an experiential conception of place shouldn’t have to contradict recent
innovations in network theory. The manifold “nodes” which make up a network are
like places, they are locations which gather intersecting spaces. However, a
place is also, itself, a network. De Certeau’s “instantaneous coexistence” of
things qualifies this and so too does Foucault in the concept of the “site”
defined by, ‘relations of proximity between points or elements; formally, we
can describe these relations as series, trees, or grids’ (Foucault, 1986: 23).
This replaces previous modes of spatial engagement such as “extension” and
“localization”, and is further elaborated by Casey’s assertion that, ‘[a] thing
is not merely in a place - that is the important but not the exhaustive
sense of place-as-container that Aristotle was to adopt in his Physics -
but a thing constitutes its (own) place’ (Casey, 1993: 16). On a
phenomenological plane, as demonstrated in Wordsworth, Joanna’s Rock is
constituted by a relationship between a series of things; nearness to Rotha’s
Bank, the presence of the narrator, the effect of Joanna’s laugh echoing off
the rock. These things do not occupy Joanna’s Rock, but they are
Joanna’s Rock. The “magic power” in its name captures the ephemerality of this
instantaneous network, an ephemerality intrinsic to what Galloway and Thacker
identify as the ‘most insubstantial of substances’ (Galloway and Thacker, 2007:
37), the “nothing” that characterises relations.
Perhaps
this is no different from de Certeau’s “creation of nowhere” in spatial
practice. This sense of becoming-nothing is what animates the moment to moment
recreation of places, the recognition of a space of indeterminacy within places
open to Ozymandian contingency. As a habitation of time and space, place
possesses the largest potential for a confrontation with difference; this is to
recognise the nowhere that permeates the where. Their becoming-nothing signifies
not a void, but a mortality, an existential presence. To politicise place would
be to unleash this heterotopic potential, one that confronts fixity and
homogeneity.
Yet, the
heterotopia, as expounded by Foucault, cannot be a simple model of place-making.
The museum is one example of a heterotopia, described as places
...in which time never stops building
up and topping its own summit [...] the idea of accumulating everything [...]
the will to enclose in one place all times, all epochs, all forms, all tastes,
the idea of constituting a place of all times that is itself outside of time
and inaccessible to its ravages, the project of organizing in this way a sort
of perpetual and indefinite accumulation of time in an immobile place, this
whole idea belongs to our modernity.
(Foucault, 1986: 26)
This perpetual “will to
enclose” and preserve mirrors a false enlightenment ideal of creating a
universal narrative of upward progress. It is place as created and maintained
by the control mechanisms of authority, a zombified space defiant of
contingency and difference. The experience of heterotopic dread is expressed by
Robert Smithson
Visiting a museum is a matter of going
from void to void. Hallways lead viewers to things once called “pictures” and
“statues.” Anachronisms hang and protrude from every angle. Themes without
meaning press on the eye. [...] Museums are tombs, and it looks like everything
is turning into a museum.
(Smithson, 1996: 41-42)
The fatalistic language used
here emphasises an underlying biopolitical aspect to place. As Heidegger shows
place to be a product of life through the indistinguishability of dwelling and
building, Smithson presents the museum as a kind of antithesis of this, a form
of power over life. Indeed, there is a parallel experience in example of the
music festival; in being kept alive it has lost its original heterotopic
qualities and its autonomy. The vast archive of dead stories, immortally on
show is the reverse of (re)created places, which, in contrast, possess, ‘fragmentary
and inward-turning histories, pasts that others are not allowed to read,
accumulated times that can be unfolded but like stories held in reserve,
remaining in an enigmatic state’ (de Certeau, 1988: 108). Secret pasts are an
exploit (Galloway and Thacker, 2007: 81) in the mechanisms of control
societies, an indeterminate life in places that resists control. The “imperial
science” behind map-making, a sort of deadening of space, cannot entirely
capture the practice of place-making which (like the Temporary Autonomous Zone)
maintains ‘an affinity for the genius loci’ (Bey, 2017).
The
keeping-alive of otherwise dead places via the mechanisms of control societies
is a
A kind of life-support machine.
A politics of place should recognise this approach the concept not as
indicative of fixity, but of indeterminate contingency. Rather than a
transcendental category, place is an assemblage whose agency results in its own
naming by a subject. It is a bounded set of material relations remade moment to
moment by differing subjectivities. The act of naming brings those relations
into a unity, a oneness, which in turn recognises the spaces it creates,
providing lines of flight. In the name is the “magic” indeterminacy, a
withdrawn nature, an inorganic vitality to which control and power are
anathema. The
zombification of space is a process which converts, ‘the organic cosmos into a
clockwork universe’ (Bey, 2017), where place is not an expression of life, but
a seizure of it. Augé’s “non-place” reflects this total cancellation of place,
yet, ‘it never exists in pure form; places reconstitute themselves in it’
(Augé, 1995: 78).
The
various thinkers engaged with over the course of this essay all capture some
vital essence about the politics of place in the era the control society.
Whilst Bey establishes a good model for spatial politics in the Temporary
Autonomous Zone, its guerrilla tactics are presented as means rather than ends,
exceptions rather than the rule. The politics of place need to be widened to
engage place on the day-to-day basis of everyday life. This includes not just
the creation of new places, but a realisation that existing places are
interdependent on continued dwelling and possess a level of autonomy. A
recognition of this autonomy is a recognition of the nowhere in somewhere, the
multiplicity of experience, both within its geographical boundaries and without
(via remembering), both human and non-human. Like the self for Deleuze and
Guattari, place is ‘a threshold, a door, a becoming between two multiplicities’
(Deleuze and Guattari, 2013: 291). Hence, the vitality in place is not a link
to identity, a totalised selfhood, but an opening onto difference. This is the
heterotopic potential within every somewhere.
Bibliography
Augé, M (1995) Non-places: introduction to an anthropology
of supermodernity, London: Verso.
Bey, H. (2017) ‘T.A.Z. : the
Temporary Autonomous Zone, ontological anarchy, poetic terrorism by Hakim Bey’,
Hermetic Library, URL:
<https://hermetic.com/bey/taz3#labelWillToPower> [Accessed 10/05/2018].
Casey, E. (1993) Getting Back into Place: toward a renewed
understanding of the Place-World, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
De Certeau, M. (1988) The Practice of Everyday Life, Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Deleuze, G. and Guattari, F.
(2013) A Thousand Plateaus, London:
Bloomsbury.
Deleuze, G. (1995) ‘Postscript
on Control Societies’ in Negotiations,
1972-1990, New York: Columbia University Press.
Foucault, M. (2002) ‘Space,
Knowledge, and Power’ in Power: The
essential works of Michel Foucault 1954-1984, volume 3, London: Penguin.
Foucault, M. and Miskowiec, J.
(1986) ‘Of Other Spaces’, Diacritics,
16(1): 22-27.
Friedler, D. (2018) ‘Music
Festivals are the Corporate Dystopia we Deserve’, The Outline, <https://theoutline.com/post/4215/music-festivals-dystopia-coachella>
[Accessed 07/05/2018].
Galloway, A. R. and Thacker, E.
(2007) The Exploit: A Theory of Networks,
Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Publishing.
Heidegger, M. ‘Building
Dwelling Thinking’ in Heidegger, M. (2013) Poetry,
Language, Thought, New York: Harper Perennial.
Smithson, R. ‘Some Void
thoughts on Museums’ in Flam, J. (ed.) (1996) Robert Smithson: The Collected Writings, Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Wordsworth, W. (2006) The Collected Poems of William Wordsworth,
Ware: Wordsworth Editions.
_________________________________________________________,
‘To Joanna’ pp: 170-172.
Comments
Post a Comment